Communities

Writing
Writing
Codidact Meta
Codidact Meta
The Great Outdoors
The Great Outdoors
Photography & Video
Photography & Video
Scientific Speculation
Scientific Speculation
Cooking
Cooking
Electrical Engineering
Electrical Engineering
Judaism
Judaism
Languages & Linguistics
Languages & Linguistics
Software Development
Software Development
Mathematics
Mathematics
Christianity
Christianity
Code Golf
Code Golf
Music
Music
Physics
Physics
Linux Systems
Linux Systems
Power Users
Power Users
Tabletop RPGs
Tabletop RPGs
Community Proposals
Community Proposals
tag:snake search within a tag
answers:0 unanswered questions
user:xxxx search by author id
score:0.5 posts with 0.5+ score
"snake oil" exact phrase
votes:4 posts with 4+ votes
created:<1w created < 1 week ago
post_type:xxxx type of post
Search help
Notifications
Mark all as read See all your notifications »
Q&A

Post History

#4: Post edited by user avatar thelast19digitsofpi‭ · 2021-06-06T23:07:58Z (over 3 years ago)
Fixed formatting of dollar signs
Why paradoxical to accept \$3, and avoid betting on Dushanbe's temperature for a prize of \$10?
  • If you don't know Dushanbe's past or historical temperatures, then isn't it rational to accept the $3 for sure? It doesn't feel rational to bet whether the temperature's low or high in Dushanbe, when you have no clue which side is more probable.
  • I don't understand why there's a paradox. If you know New York's historical temperatures, then you have more chance of predicting which side of the bet is correct.
  • >&nbsp; &nbsp; &nbsp; Economists have often wondered about decisions involving uncertainty versus risk and the distinction between the implications of evidence and the weight of evidence. American economist Daniel Ellsberg drew attention to the difficulty of modeling ambiguity (his term) using subjective probability with an elegant paradox.
  • &nbsp; &nbsp; &nbsp; In one version (Hsu et al., 2005), subjects were asked whether they would rather have \$3 for sure or choose to bet \$10 that the temperature was _above_ 55 degrees or _below_ 55 degrees in New York on a particular day (i.e., they would win \$10 if they were right). Other subjects were asked a similar question, but about the temperature in Dushanbe, Tajikistan. More subjects chose to bet on New York rather than on Tajikistan.
  • &nbsp; &nbsp; &nbsp; Call the New York bet “risky” and the Dushanbe bet “ambiguous.” Subjects generally preferred to bet on either side of the New York bet (i.e., above or below) and to avoid the Dushanbe bet. This was a paradox$^4$ because if they didn’t want to bet that Dushanbe was low, and their beliefs about _Probability _ (low in Dushanbe) + _Probability_ (high in Dushanbe) add to 1, they should logically have been eager to bet that Dushanbe was high.
  • Paul Slovic, *The Irrational Economist* (2010), p 84.
  • >$^4$ In other words, it is possible that they generally knew more about New York temperatures, such that the maximum of p (low in NY) and p (high in NY) was higher than the maximum of p (low in Dushanbe) and p (high in Dushanbe), but in actuality they were not more accurate about the high-information bets
  • Op. cit. p 285.
  • If you don't know Dushanbe's past or historical temperatures, then isn't it rational to accept the $3 for sure? It doesn't feel rational to bet whether the temperature's low or high in Dushanbe, when you have no clue which side is more probable.
  • I don't understand why there's a paradox. If you know New York's historical temperatures, then you have more chance of predicting which side of the bet is correct.
  • >&nbsp; &nbsp; &nbsp; Economists have often wondered about decisions involving uncertainty versus risk and the distinction between the implications of evidence and the weight of evidence. American economist Daniel Ellsberg drew attention to the difficulty of modeling ambiguity (his term) using subjective probability with an elegant paradox.
  • &nbsp; &nbsp; &nbsp; In one version (Hsu et al., 2005), subjects were asked whether they would rather have \\$3 for sure or choose to bet \$10 that the temperature was _above_ 55 degrees or _below_ 55 degrees in New York on a particular day (i.e., they would win \\$10 if they were right). Other subjects were asked a similar question, but about the temperature in Dushanbe, Tajikistan. More subjects chose to bet on New York rather than on Tajikistan.
  • &nbsp; &nbsp; &nbsp; Call the New York bet “risky” and the Dushanbe bet “ambiguous.” Subjects generally preferred to bet on either side of the New York bet (i.e., above or below) and to avoid the Dushanbe bet. This was a paradox$^4$ because if they didn’t want to bet that Dushanbe was low, and their beliefs about _Probability _ (low in Dushanbe) + _Probability_ (high in Dushanbe) add to 1, they should logically have been eager to bet that Dushanbe was high.
  • Paul Slovic, *The Irrational Economist* (2010), p 84.
  • >$^4$ In other words, it is possible that they generally knew more about New York temperatures, such that the maximum of p (low in NY) and p (high in NY) was higher than the maximum of p (low in Dushanbe) and p (high in Dushanbe), but in actuality they were not more accurate about the high-information bets
  • Op. cit. p 285.
#3: Post edited by user avatar Chgg Clou‭ · 2021-06-06T07:09:44Z (over 3 years ago)
  • Why's paradoxical to accept \$3, and avoid betting on Dushanbe's temperature for a prize of \$10?
  • Why paradoxical to accept \$3, and avoid betting on Dushanbe's temperature for a prize of \$10?
#2: Post edited by user avatar Chgg Clou‭ · 2021-06-06T06:59:33Z (over 3 years ago)
  • Why's paradoxical to accept $3, and avoid betting on Dushanbe's temperature for a prize of $10?
  • Why's paradoxical to accept \$3, and avoid betting on Dushanbe's temperature for a prize of \$10?
#1: Initial revision by user avatar Chgg Clou‭ · 2021-06-06T06:58:34Z (over 3 years ago)
Why's paradoxical to accept $3, and avoid betting on Dushanbe's temperature for a prize of $10?
If you don't know Dushanbe's past or historical temperatures, then isn't it rational to accept the $3 for sure? It doesn't feel rational to bet whether the temperature's low or high in Dushanbe, when you have no clue which side is more probable. 

I don't understand why there's a paradox. If you know New York's historical temperatures, then you have more chance of predicting which side of the bet is correct. 

>&nbsp; &nbsp; &nbsp; Economists have often wondered about decisions involving uncertainty versus risk and the distinction between the implications of evidence and the weight of evidence. American economist Daniel Ellsberg drew attention to the difficulty of modeling ambiguity (his term) using subjective probability with an elegant paradox.   
&nbsp; &nbsp; &nbsp; In one version (Hsu et al., 2005), subjects were asked whether they would rather have \$3 for sure or choose to bet \$10 that the temperature was _above_ 55 degrees or _below_ 55 degrees in New York on a particular day (i.e., they would win \$10 if they were right). Other subjects were asked a similar question, but about the temperature in Dushanbe, Tajikistan. More subjects chose to bet on New York rather than on Tajikistan.      
&nbsp; &nbsp; &nbsp; Call the New York bet “risky” and the Dushanbe bet “ambiguous.” Subjects generally preferred to bet on either side of the New York bet (i.e., above or below) and to avoid the Dushanbe bet. This was a paradox$^4$ because if they didn’t want to bet that Dushanbe was low, and their beliefs about _Probability _ (low in Dushanbe) + _Probability_ (high in Dushanbe) add to 1, they should logically have been eager to bet that Dushanbe was high.

Paul Slovic, *The Irrational Economist* (2010), p 84.

>$^4$ In other words, it is possible that they generally knew more about New York temperatures, such that the maximum of p (low in NY) and p (high in NY) was higher than the maximum of p (low in Dushanbe) and p (high in Dushanbe), but in actuality they were not more accurate about the high-information bets

Op. cit. p 285.