Communities

Writing
Writing
Codidact Meta
Codidact Meta
The Great Outdoors
The Great Outdoors
Photography & Video
Photography & Video
Scientific Speculation
Scientific Speculation
Cooking
Cooking
Electrical Engineering
Electrical Engineering
Judaism
Judaism
Languages & Linguistics
Languages & Linguistics
Software Development
Software Development
Mathematics
Mathematics
Christianity
Christianity
Code Golf
Code Golf
Music
Music
Physics
Physics
Linux Systems
Linux Systems
Power Users
Power Users
Tabletop RPGs
Tabletop RPGs
Community Proposals
Community Proposals
tag:snake search within a tag
answers:0 unanswered questions
user:xxxx search by author id
score:0.5 posts with 0.5+ score
"snake oil" exact phrase
votes:4 posts with 4+ votes
created:<1w created < 1 week ago
post_type:xxxx type of post
Search help
Notifications
Mark all as read See all your notifications »
Q&A

What is a “first-order substructural logic that has a cut-free sequent calculus”?

+0
−3

Is a first order sub-structural logic a synonym for a fragment of first order logic? Ie just some restriction on syntactic allowances, so we know we have a theory whose sentences are a subset of the theory of FOL?

I read that in sequent calculus, a cut rule is a rather trivial sounding rule that if you have A proves B, and B proves C, you can write A proves C.

Why would eliminating the cut rule be significant? Even without the cut rule, if A proves B, and B proves C, shouldn’t it be possible to show a direct proof of C from A, without the “cut rule”, which sounds like a mere convenience method? What are examples of theorems that cannot be proven without the cut rule?

History
Why does this post require attention from curators or moderators?
You might want to add some details to your flag.
Why should this post be closed?

0 comment threads

1 answer

+2
−0

The structural rules of sequent calculus are:

  • Weakening: $$\dfrac{Γ ⊢ C}{Γ, A ⊢ C}$$

  • Contraction: $$\dfrac{Γ, A, A ⊢ C}{Γ, A ⊢ C}$$

  • Exchange: $$\dfrac{Γ, A, B ⊢ C}{Γ, B, A ⊢ C}$$

Substructural logics omit at least one of these rules.

As for cut elimination, part of the point is that it is a proof that the cut rule is merely a 'convenience.' That requires actual proof, not just 'seeming.' Also, the cut rule is a bit more complicated than you've stated. It is more like:

  • Cut: $$\dfrac{Γ,A,Γ' ⊢ C \qquad Δ ⊢ A}{Γ,Δ,Γ' ⊢ C}$$

So, for instance, let's also consider substructural logics. How certain are you, exactly, that cutting like that in the middle of a context never expands into a cut-free proof that makes use of the "exchange" rule to reorder the premises in the context?

If the consequent were instead $$Γ,Γ',Δ ⊢ C$$ then we'd pretty easily be able to derive exchange, and cut could not be eliminated without the exchange rule. So that is a sort of contrived example of why a cut-like rule would not be able to be eliminated. There are other 'bad' ways to design sequent rules that prevent eliminating cut as well. So proving cut elimination is sort of a check that you have designed your proof rules in a good way, so that cut is "just" a convenience.

However, do also note that in the presence of contraction, cut-free proofs can easily be exponentially larger than the original. So it can be a very significant convenience. One could even argue that it is not realistic to imagine that cut can be eliminated for this reason, because some cut-free proofs would be too large to write down. But, this is usually not a concern in the idealized setting used for analyzing logics.

History
Why does this post require attention from curators or moderators?
You might want to add some details to your flag.

0 comment threads

Sign up to answer this question »