Communities

Writing
Writing
Codidact Meta
Codidact Meta
The Great Outdoors
The Great Outdoors
Photography & Video
Photography & Video
Scientific Speculation
Scientific Speculation
Cooking
Cooking
Electrical Engineering
Electrical Engineering
Judaism
Judaism
Languages & Linguistics
Languages & Linguistics
Software Development
Software Development
Mathematics
Mathematics
Christianity
Christianity
Code Golf
Code Golf
Music
Music
Physics
Physics
Linux Systems
Linux Systems
Power Users
Power Users
Tabletop RPGs
Tabletop RPGs
Community Proposals
Community Proposals
tag:snake search within a tag
answers:0 unanswered questions
user:xxxx search by author id
score:0.5 posts with 0.5+ score
"snake oil" exact phrase
votes:4 posts with 4+ votes
created:<1w created < 1 week ago
post_type:xxxx type of post
Search help
Notifications
Mark all as read See all your notifications »
Q&A

Post History

#1: Initial revision by user avatar Derek Elkins‭ · 2022-08-21T00:59:12Z (over 2 years ago)
You can't do induction on the real numbers because the real numbers aren't inductively defined. That said, it's not clear what you intend "induction on reals" to mean.

Before continuing, I'd like to make an aside on proof writing. First, as a matter of presentation, it's useful to make it clear what theorem you are attempting to prove and nice to actually conclude with deducing the stated theorem. Hence the traditional "**Theorem**: ... **Proof**: ... **Q.E.D.**" structure. In your question, while it's clear that you ultimately want to prove $e^x \ge x+1$, it's not clear that this is what the boxed reasoning at the bottom is supposed conclude, nor does that reasoning actually conclude with that statement. This leads to the next, more fundamental point.

Proofs are not a series of statements but a series of steps of reasoning. In your first chain of implications, to be a proof, each of those implications should be explicitly justified by some reasoning. In practice, filling in simple steps of reasoning is often left to the reader, so your presentation of that chain of implications is fine enough (though there are definitely subtleties that your presentation glosses over, e.g. when we take the reciprocal of both sides, the resulting inequality is no longer true for all $x$). Nevertheless, you should generally be biased toward being more explicit about the steps of reasoning, especially when you are uncertain and/or those steps are more complicated or subtle. This helps you catch mistakes, helps others catch mistakes, and, ultimately, is just what a proof is.

For induction over the naturals, the relevant proof rule is $$\dfrac{P(0) \qquad \forall n.P(n) \implies P(n+1)}{\forall n.P(n)}$$ If you aren't familiar with this notation for our purposes here it can be read as "if we've proven the statements on the top, then this rule proves the statement on the bottom". Alternatively, we can present induction as an axiom schema: $(P(0) \land (\forall n.P(n) \implies P(n+1))) \implies \forall n. P(n)$.

To use induction, we need to state which formula we're substituting for $P$ at which point we need to prove the two statements $P(0)$ and $\forall n.P(n) \implies P(n+1)$. Having done that, we may conclude, via induction, that $\forall n. P(n)$ holds.

For your "real number induction", you'd need to state what the rule is, prove it itself or give reference to a proof, and then show how you are instantiating the rule and the resolve any proof obligations the rule entails.

For actually solving the problem, i.e. proving $e^x \ge x + 1$, it's useful to have a definition for $e^x$. For example, one definition would be that it is the unique function satisfying $Df = f$ and $f(0)=1$, but that's not too useful for your purposes. Another definition would be $e^x \equiv \sum_{n=0}^\infty x^n/n!$. This definition makes it relatively easy to see that $e^x \ge x + 1$. It's immediately obvious for $x \ge 0$. You can prove $e^{x+y}=e^x e^y$ directly from the power series, from which you can prove $e^{-x} = 1/e^x$ from which $e^x > 0$ follows for all $x\in \mathbb R$. That establishes $e^x \ge x + 1$ for $x \le -1$. The only remaining case is when $x\in(-1,0)$. For this range of $x$, we can simply directly show that $\sum_{n=2}^\infty x^n/n!$ (note the index starting point) is bounded below by $0$, e.g. with an induction over the partial sums.