Communities

Writing
Writing
Codidact Meta
Codidact Meta
The Great Outdoors
The Great Outdoors
Photography & Video
Photography & Video
Scientific Speculation
Scientific Speculation
Cooking
Cooking
Electrical Engineering
Electrical Engineering
Judaism
Judaism
Languages & Linguistics
Languages & Linguistics
Software Development
Software Development
Mathematics
Mathematics
Christianity
Christianity
Code Golf
Code Golf
Music
Music
Physics
Physics
Linux Systems
Linux Systems
Power Users
Power Users
Tabletop RPGs
Tabletop RPGs
Community Proposals
Community Proposals
tag:snake search within a tag
answers:0 unanswered questions
user:xxxx search by author id
score:0.5 posts with 0.5+ score
"snake oil" exact phrase
votes:4 posts with 4+ votes
created:<1w created < 1 week ago
post_type:xxxx type of post
Search help
Notifications
Mark all as read See all your notifications »
Q&A

Post History

#1: Initial revision by user avatar Derek Elkins‭ · 2021-06-05T02:05:16Z (over 3 years ago)
Consider the universal quantifier. I'll write it as: $\mathsf{forall}\ x.P(x)$ to be read as "for all $x$ in the domain $P(x)$ holds". We then have the logical identity $$(\mathsf{forall}\ x.P(x)) \land (\mathsf{forall}\ x.Q(x)) \to (\mathsf{forall}\ x. P(x) \land Q(x))$$ where $\land$ is logical conjunction and $\to$ is logical implication. Let's have the domain be people and $P(x)$ mean "$x$ want $A$" and $Q(x)$ mean "$x$ wants $B$". We can then read the above condition as: "if everybody wants $A$ and everybody wants $B$, then everybody wants $A$ and $B$".

If, however, we consider a majority quantifier, write it as $\mathsf{most}\ x. P(x)$, meaning "$P(x)$ holds for 'most' $x$", we do *not* have an identity similar to the above. Using the same intepretation as before, we'd get a statement like "if most people want $A$ and most people want $B$, then most people want $A$ and $B$" which does NOT hold in general. The people who want both is the intersection between the people who want each individually, and while this intersection is guaranteed to be non-empty it's certainly not guaranteed to be a majority. It's easy to imagine a situation where three out of five of your friends want to eat pizza for lunch, and three out of five want to go to the park in the evening, but only one wants to do both.

Scalia's argument could then potentially be interpreted as: "Most states think the death penalty should be allowed and most states treat these groups the same, therefore most states think the death penalty should be allowed with no distinction between these groups of people." This statement doesn't follow.