Communities

Writing
Writing
Codidact Meta
Codidact Meta
The Great Outdoors
The Great Outdoors
Photography & Video
Photography & Video
Scientific Speculation
Scientific Speculation
Cooking
Cooking
Electrical Engineering
Electrical Engineering
Judaism
Judaism
Languages & Linguistics
Languages & Linguistics
Software Development
Software Development
Mathematics
Mathematics
Christianity
Christianity
Code Golf
Code Golf
Music
Music
Physics
Physics
Linux Systems
Linux Systems
Power Users
Power Users
Tabletop RPGs
Tabletop RPGs
Community Proposals
Community Proposals
tag:snake search within a tag
answers:0 unanswered questions
user:xxxx search by author id
score:0.5 posts with 0.5+ score
"snake oil" exact phrase
votes:4 posts with 4+ votes
created:<1w created < 1 week ago
post_type:xxxx type of post
Search help
Notifications
Mark all as read See all your notifications »
Q&A

Post History

#1: Initial revision by user avatar celtschk‭ · 2021-03-09T09:20:44Z (about 3 years ago)
One thing to consider is that the equivalences are generally based on the validity of certain axioms. And then, one direction may only depend on a smaller set of axioms. Now it is possible that the additional axioms help also in the direction that doesn't need it,  but it is also possible that the easiest proof still relies only on that smaller set of axioms. Obviously if you effectively start with a different premise (the larger set of axioms plus the property rather than the smaller set of axioms plus the property) that may affect the difficulty of the proof (in either way).

Take for example the Cauchy convergence example you mentioned. It clearly rests on the axioms of the real numbers. If you relax those axioms to, say, those of an ordered field (that is, remove the axiom that the real numbers are complete), then the equivalence does *no longer* hold, as the rational numbers show: They are an ordered field in which *not* all sequences converge (a sequence of rational numbers can converge to an irrational number).

On the other hand, the fact that all convergent series are Cauchy series also holds in ordered fields. Therefore the equivalence does *not* hold in arbitrary ordered fields, but one of the directions can be proved already there.

Now whether the proof that all Cauchy sequences convergence is harder of easier depends on which construction of the real numbers (that is, which set of axioms) you use. If you construct the real numbers through Cauchy sequences, then the proof that each Cauchy sequence converges is trivial: That's how you constructed the real numbers, after all! But if you construct the real numbers by another way (for example, with Dedekind cuts, or with nested intervals), the proof may be more involved.

For better illustration, let's use another equivalence, this time in the natural numbers. The theorem is simple:

> An even number is larger than 2 iff it is larger than 3.

Of course the proof is also simple, but it still is easier in one direction:

> $\implies$: A natural number larger than 2 either equals 3 or is larger than 3. But 3 is not even, therefore all even numbers larger than 2 are also larger than 3.

> $\impliedby$: Any number that is larger than 3 is also larger than 2. This obviously also holds for even numbers.

Clearly the $\impliedby$ direction is simpler (though not by much). And it is simpler precisely because we didn't even have to use the definition of “even”, nor any properties of the natural numbers other than that they are totally ordered and that $3>2$.

----

Another case where the two directions generally have different difficulty is when an existence statement is involved. To prove “there does exist” all you have to do is to provide an example, which often (but not always!) is easy. On the other hand, when taking “there exists” as condition, this is equivalent to proving the *nonexistence* when the equivalent condition is not fulfilled. Obviously proving nonexistence can be very hard, as the negation of a “there exists” statement is a “for all” statement.